Skip to content

Generalization and Abstraction

June 8, 2012

[cm] Generalization vs. Abstraction

Posina Venkata Rayudu posina at salk.edu

Dear All,

In the following I’ll make an attempt to answer Prof. Tim Porter‘s question: ‘What is Abstraction?’

Let an object O have a collection of properties P = {p1, p2, …, pi, …}, each of which could be any of the familiar (or unfamiliar) properties like length, weight, etc. From this we can go on to say that each one of the properties pi in the collection of properties P takes a value vi, i.e. pi = vi, which is basically like saying the weight of the object O is 10 kg or something like that. Now a generalization of the object O along a property pi would be an object Og, whose property pi is not constrained to take the value vi i.e. not restricted to pi = vi.

Abstraction, on the other hand, of the object O along the property pi would be an object Oa, whose collection of properties Pa doesn’t include pi. More explicitly, the collection of properties of an abstraction Oa is given by Pa = {p1, p2, …}.

In the attached (Number2Function) I tried to illustrate Abstraction in terms of an example: abstracting the notion of FUNCTION from the concept of NUMBER.

I’d appreciate very much any corrections and clarifications that you can, your time permitting, provide.

Thanking you,
Yours sincerely,
posina

P.S. Hope to see you all bright and early tomorrow morning!

P. P.S. I hope the above along with the attached note is anything but an abuse of some concept[s]. In Conceptual Mathematics there’s a warning against abusing in ‘Two Abuses of Isomorphisms’ on p. 89.
NumberToFunction.pdf

About these ads

From → Note to self

8 Comments
  1. Subject: Re: [cm] Generalization vs. Abstraction
    Date: Mon, 1 Aug 2011 21:30:43 -0500
    From: Charles Wells
    To: Posina Venkata Rayudu

    You were right about generalization: Allowing a fixed property to vary, or simply be dropped. Abstraction is more radical than what you described. An abstraction of an idea defined by certain requirements (axioms)
    r1, r2,…rn
    consists of finding a *different* list of properties, often *completely* different, such that the objects satisfying the original axioms all have those new properties, but there are also objects satisfying the new properties that don’t satisfy the original ones.

    For example, a continuous function on a metric space can be defined by requiring that it satisfies the usual epsilon-delta definition. But you can define it in more general topological spaces by requiring that the inverse of open sets must be open. This way of saying it doesn’t mention the distance between points and so works for spaces than are not metric spaces. But it is equivalent to the original definition for metric spaces.

    My article at

    http://www.abstractmath.org/MM/MMOtherAspectsUnderstanding.htm#abstraction

    talks about this and gives pointers to some examples.

    Charles Wells

Trackbacks & Pingbacks

  1. On choosing from a menu « Conceptual Mathematics
  2. Quantity : Space :: Quality : ? « Conceptual Mathematics
  3. Reinventing the wheel « Conceptual Mathematics
  4. second coming « Conceptual Mathematics
  5. Abstract circumlocution « Conceptual Mathematics
  6. HOW MINDS THEORIZE: I. Opposites | Conceptual Mathematics

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s

Follow

Get every new post delivered to your Inbox.

Join 1,200 other followers

%d bloggers like this: